Epistemological Explorations in the Context of Religious Diversity
Keywords:
Epistemology, Evidence, Justification, Naturalism, Religious Experience, William AlstonAbstract
Ever since modern epistemology, with its scientistic orientation and foundationalist structure, took centre stage, religion has been on the defensive. Although both these features of modern epistemology have been challenged in the more recent times, it has not yet restored the credibility of religious knowledge. Briefly looking at William Alston’s attempt at doing epistemology of religious experience in the changed circumstances, it is seen that diversity (religious and otherwise) poses a serious challenge to his efforts. This paper explores how epistemology of religious experience may be further fine-tuned by naturalizing it. Since public evidence plays a crucial role in the emerging theory of epistemic justification, it is dubbed evidential naturalism. An initial exposition of evidential naturalism is provided.
References
George Karuvelil, “Christian Faith, Philosophy, and Culture: The Triumphs and Failures of Wisdom,” Jnanadeepa 17, 1 (2014), 101-118.
William P. Alston, “Back to the Theory of Appearing,” Nous 33, Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives 13 (1999).
William P. Alston, “The Autonomy of Religious Experience,” International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 31, 2-3 (1992), 68. For the sake of brevity, I leave out Alston’s elaborate and important discussion of doxastic practices.
William P. Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1991, 6, 100.
William P. Alston, Epistemic Justification, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1989, 7; Alston, Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience, 71.
Terence Penelhum, “Parity Is Not Enough” in Faith, Reason, and Skepticism: Essays by William P. Alston, Robert Audi, Terence Penelhum, Richard H. Popkin, ed. Marcus B. Hester, Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992, 111.
Aquinas, Summa Contra Gentiles, Book I, chapter 2.
Hilary Putnam, Reason, Truth, and History, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981, 49.
Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences, London: Routledge, 2002, xvi. W. V. Quine, “In Praise of Observation Sentences,” The Journal of Philosophy 90, 3 (1993), 107.
W. V. Quine, From Stimulus to Science, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1995, 21; W. V. Quine, “I, You, and It: An Epistemological Triangle” in Knowledge, Language and Logic: Questions for Quine, eds. Alex Orenstein and Petr Kotatko, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2000, 1, 2, 408. Robert Audi explicitly uses the word ‘natural’ for similar instances of knowledge. Robert Audi, Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed., New York: Routledge, 2003, 237.
Noah Marcelino Lemos, Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense, Cambridge Studies in Philosophy, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004.
W. V. Quine, The Roots of Reference, LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1973, 3. It may be noted that Reid anticipates Quine when he distinguished “orginal” or primitive perceptions from the acquired ones. See, Lorne Falkenstein, “Nativism and the Nature of Thought in Reid’s Account of Our Knowledge of the External World,” in The Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid, eds. Terence Cuneo and René van Woudenberg, New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004, 159.
James Maffie, “Recent Work on Naturalized Epistemology,” American Philosophical Quarterly 27, 4 (1990), 281-93.
Stephen Everson, ed., Epistemology: Companions to Ancient Thought, vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge Univeristy Press, 1990, 6; Barry Maund, Perception: Central Problems of Philosophy, Chesham, Bucks: Acumen, 2003, 3.
Ronald Giere, “Modest Evolutionary Naturalism” in Naturalized Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, eds. Chienkuo Mi and Ruey-lin Chen, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2007, 25.
Karl R. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London/New York: Routledge, 1992, 7.
Peter Lipton, Inference to the Best Explanation, 2nd ed., London, New York: Routledge/Taylor and Francis Group, 2004.
William F. Brewer and Bruce L. Lambert, “The Theory-Ladenness of Observation and the Theory-Ladenness of the Rest of the Scientific Process,” Philosophy of Science 68, 3 (2001), S176-S186; see also, Carl R. Kordig, “The Theory-Ladenness of Observation,” The Review of Metaphysics 24, 3 (1971), 448-484; “Observational Invariance,” Philosophy of Science 40, 4 (1973), 558-569.
Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind, New York: Routledge, 2009, 6.